HimplHeap Entailment

Set Implicit Arguments.
From SLF Require LibSepReference.
From SLF Require Export Hprop.

First Pass

In the previous chapter, we introduced the type hprop and the key operators over this type: \[], \[P], p ~~> v, H1 \* H2, Q1 \*+ H2, and \ x, H.
In order to state the reasoning rules of Separation Logic, we need to introduce the "entailment relation" on heap predicates. This relation, written H1 ==> H2, asserts that any heap that satisfies H1 also satisfies H2. We also need to extend the entailment relation to postconditions. We write Q1 ===> Q2 to asserts that, for any result value v, the entailment Q1 v ==> Q2 v holds.
Both entailment relations ==> and ===> appear in the statement of the "consequence-frame rule", exploited by the tactic xapp for reasoning about every function call. This rule explains how to derive a triple of the form triple t H Q, knowing that the term t admits the specification triple t H1 Q1. There are two requirements: First, the precondition H must decompose into H1, which denotes the precondition expected by the specification, and some remaining part, H2. Second, the targeted postcondition Q must be a consequence of the conjunction of Q1, which denotes the postcondition asserted by the specification, and H2, which again denotes the remaining part, which should not have been affected during the evaluation of the term t.
The formal statement of the frame rule is as follows.
    Lemma triple_conseq_frame : H2 H1 Q1 t H Q,
      triple t H1 Q1
      H ==> (H1 \* H2) →
      (Q1 \*+ H2) ===> Q
      triple t H Q.
This chapter presents:
  • the formal definition of the entailment relations for heap predicates and for postconditions,
  • the lemmas capturing the interaction of entailment with the star operator, and
  • the features of the tactics xsimpl and xchange, which are critically useful for manipulating entailments in practice.
The tactics xsimpl and xchange were already used in the first two chapters. The implementation of these tactics (from LibSepSimpl.v) is out of scope for the present course, but in this chapter we explore their features in more depth through examples.
This chapter exploits one additional TLC tactic for improving scripts: applys is an enhanced version of eapply. This tactic takes as argument a lemma or hypothesis, plus (optionally) a variable number of arguments, which are fed to the lemma on a first-match basis. In other words, applys L x y is equivalent to eapply (L _ _ .. _ x _ _ .. _ _ y _ _ ..) for an appropriate number of underscore symbols.

Definition of Entailment

The entailment relationship H1 ==> H2 asserts that any heap h that satisfies the heap predicate H1 also satisfies H2.
Definition himpl (H1 H2:hprop) : Prop :=
   (h:heap), H1 h H2 h.

Notation "H1 ==> H2" := (himpl H1 H2) (at level 55).
Entailment is reflexive, transitive, and antisymmetric. It thus forms an order relation on heap predicates.
Lemma himpl_refl : H,
  H ==> H.
Proof using. intros h. hnf. auto. Qed.

Lemma himpl_trans : H2 H1 H3,
  (H1 ==> H2)
  (H2 ==> H3)
  (H1 ==> H3).
Proof using. introv M1 M2. intros h H1h. eauto. Qed.

Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (himpl_antisym)

Prove the antisymmetry of entailment result shown below. Hint: use predicate_extensionality.
Lemma himpl_antisym : H1 H2,
  (H1 ==> H2)
  (H2 ==> H1)
  H1 = H2.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Entailment for Postconditions

The entailment relation on postconditions, written Q1 ===> Q2, asserts that the heap predicate Q1 v entails Q2 v for any value v.
Definition qimpl (Q1 Q2:valhprop) : Prop :=
   (v:val), Q1 v ==> Q2 v.

Notation "Q1 ===> Q2" := (qimpl Q1 Q2) (at level 55).
In other words, Q1 ===> Q2 holds if and only if, for any value v and any heap h, the proposition Q1 v h implies Q2 v h.
Entailment on postconditions also forms an order relation:
Lemma qimpl_refl : Q,
  Q ===> Q.
Proof using. intros Q v. apply himpl_refl. Qed.

Lemma qimpl_trans : Q2 Q1 Q3,
  (Q1 ===> Q2)
  (Q2 ===> Q3)
  (Q1 ===> Q3).
Proof using. introv M1 M2. intros v. eapply himpl_trans; eauto. Qed.

Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (qimpl_antisym)

Prove the antisymmetry of entailment on postconditions. Hint: exploit functional_extensionality.
Lemma qimpl_antisym : Q1 Q2,
  (Q1 ===> Q2)
  (Q2 ===> Q1)
  (Q1 = Q2).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Frame Rule for Entailment

A fundamental property is that the star operator is monotone with respect to entailment, meaning that if H1 ==> H1' then (H1 \* H2) ==> (H1' \* H2). In other words, an arbitrary heap predicate H2 can be "framed" on both sides of an entailment.
Viewed the other way around, if we have to prove the entailment relation (H1 \* H2) ==> (H1' \* H2), we can "cancel out" H2 on both sides. In this view, the monotonicity property is a sort of frame rule for the entailment relation.
Due to commutativity of star, it suffices to state only the left version of the monotonicity property.
Parameter himpl_frame_l : H2 H1 H1',
  H1 ==> H1'
  (H1 \* H2) ==> (H1' \* H2).

Rules for Proving Entailments

The rules for introducing and eliminating pure facts and existential quantifiers in entailments are essential. They are presented next.
The first rule is captured by the lemma himpl_hstar_hpure_r. Consider an entailment of the form H ==> (\[P] \* H'). To establish this entailment, we must prove that P is true and that H entails H'.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (himpl_hstar_hpure_r).

Prove the rule himpl_hstar_hpure_r.
Hint: recall from Hprop the lemma hstar_hpure_l, which asserts the equality (\[P] \* H) h = (P H h).
Lemma himpl_hstar_hpure_r : (P:Prop) H H',
  P
  (H ==> H')
  H ==> (\[P] \* H').
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Reciprocally, consider an entailment of the form (\[P] \* H) ==> H'. To establish this entailment, we must prove that H entails H' under the assumption that P is true. The "extraction rule for pure facts in the left of an entailment" captures the property that the pure fact \[P] can be extracted into the Coq context. It is stated as follows.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (himpl_hstar_hpure_l).

Prove the rule himpl_hstar_hpure_l.
Lemma himpl_hstar_hpure_l : (P:Prop) (H H':hprop),
  (P H ==> H')
  (\[P] \* H) ==> H'.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Consider an entailment of the form H ==> (\ x, J x), where x has some type A and J has type Ahprop. To establish this entailment, we must exhibit a value for x for which H entails J x.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (himpl_hexists_r).

Prove the rule himpl_hexists_r.
Lemma himpl_hexists_r : A (x:A) H J,
  (H ==> J x)
  H ==> (\ x, J x).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Reciprocally, consider an entailment (\ x, (J x)) ==> H. To establish this entailment, one has to prove that, whatever the value of x, the predicate J x entails H. Indeed the former proposition asserts that if a heap h satisfies J x for some x, then h satisfies H', while the latter asserts that if, for some x, the predicate h satisfies J x, then h satisfies H'.
The "extraction rule for existentials in the left of an entailment" captures the property that existentials can be extracted into the Coq context. It is stated as follows. (Observe how the existential quantifier on the left of the entailment becomes a universal quantifier outside of the arrow.)

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (himpl_hexists_l).

Prove the rule himpl_hexists_l.
Lemma himpl_hexists_l : (A:Type) (H:hprop) (J:Ahprop),
  ( x, J x ==> H)
  (\ x, J x) ==> H.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Extracting Information from Heap Predicates

We next present an example showing how entailments can be used to state lemmas allowing that extract information from particular heap predicates. Concretely, we show that, from a heap predicate of the form (p ~~> v1) \* (p ~~> v2), describing two "disjoint" cells that are both "at location p", one can extract a contradiction. Indeed, such a state cannot exist.
The proof of this result exploits a result on finite maps. Essentially, the domain of a single singleton map that binds a location p to some value is the singleton set \{p}, so such a singleton map cannot be disjoint from another singleton map that binds the same location p.
    Check disjoint_single_single_same_inv : (p:loc) (v1 v2:val),
      Fmap.disjoint (Fmap.single p v1) (Fmap.single p v2) →
      False.
Using this lemma, we can prove hstar_hsingle_same_loc by unfolding the definition of hstar to reveal the contradiction on the disjointness assumption.
Proof using.
  intros. unfold hsingle. intros h (h1&h2&E1&E2&D&E). false.
  subst. eapply Fmap.disjoint_single_single_same_inv. eapply D.
Qed.
More generally, a heap predicate of the form H \* H is usually suspicious in Separation Logic. In the simple variant of Separation Logic that we consider in this course, there are only three typical situations where H \* H makes sense:
  • (1) if H is the empty heap predicate \[],
  • (2) if H is a pure heap predicate of the form \[P], or
  • (3) if H has the form \ (H0:hprop), H0, which will be written \GC in chapter Affine.

Rules for Naming Heaps

We write = h as a shorthand for fun h' h' = h, that is, the heap predicate that only accepts heaps exactly equal to h.

Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (hexists_named_eq)

Prove that a heap predicate H is equivalent to \ h, \[H h] \* (= h)).
Hint: In one direction, use hexists_intro and hstar_hpure_l. In the other, use the extraction rules himpl_hexists_l and himpl_hstar_hpure_l.
Lemma hexists_named_eq : H,
  H = (\ h, \[H h] \* (= h)).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

The xsimpl Tactic

Simplifying entailments by hand is extremely tedious. Fortunately, it can be automated using a specialized Coq tactic. This tactic, called xsimpl, applies to an entailment and implements a 3-step process:
  • extract pure facts and existential quantifiers from the LHS;
  • instantial existential quantifiers from the RHS, using either Coq unification variables or user-provided hints (details are explained further on);
  • cancel out predicates that occur on both the LHS and RHS; certain Coq unification variables may be instantiated during that process.
These steps are detailed and illustrated in the subsections that follow.
To make the xsimpl tactic available, we import the LibSepReference, over a scope delimited by the module named XsimplTactic. When doing so, the Separation Logic operators and entailments refer to the definitions from LibSepReference. These definitions are essentially the same as those presented in Hprop and earlier in the present chapter.
Module XsimplTactic.
Import LibSepReference.

xsimpl Extracts Pure Facts and Quantifiers in LHS

The first feature of xsimpl is its ability to extract the pure facts and existential quantifiers from the left-hand side out into the Coq context.
In the example below, the pure fact n > 0 appears in the LHS. After calling xsimpl, this pure fact is turned into a hypothesis, which may be introduced with a name into the Coq context.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_lhs_hpure : H1 H2 H3 H4 (n:int),
  H1 \* H2 \* \[n > 0] \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl. intros Hn.
Abort.
In case the LHS includes a contradiction, such as the pure fact False, the goal gets solved immediately by xsimpl.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_lhs_hpure : H1 H2 H3 H4,
  H1 \* H2 \* \[False] \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Qed.
The xsimpl tactic also extracts existential quantifiers from the LHS. It turns them into universally quantified variables outside of the entailment relation.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_lhs_hexists : H1 H2 H3 H4 (p:loc),
  H1 \* \ (n:int), (p ~~> n \* H2) \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl. intros n.
Abort.
A single call to xsimpl extracts all the pure facts and quantifiers from the LHS.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_lhs_several : H1 H2 H3 H4 (p q:loc),
  H1 \* \ (n:int), (p ~~> n \* \[n > 0] \* H2) \* \[p q] \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl. intros n Hn Hp.
Abort.

xsimpl Cancels Out Heap Predicates from LHS and RHS

The second feature of xsimpl is its ability to cancel out similar heap predicates that occur on both sides of an entailment.
In the example below, H2 occurs on both sides, so it is canceled out by xsimpl.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_cancel_one : H1 H2 H3 H4 H5 H6 H7,
  H1 \* H2 \* H3 \* H4 ==> H5 \* H6 \* H2 \* H7.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Abort.
xsimpl actually cancels out all the heap predicates that it can spot appearing on both sides. In the example below, H2, H3, and H4 are canceled out.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_cancel_many : H1 H2 H3 H4 H5,
  H1 \* H2 \* H3 \* H4 ==> H4 \* H3 \* H5 \* H2.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Abort.
If all the pieces of heap predicate get canceled out, the remaining proof obligation is \[] ==> \[]. In this case, xsimpl automatically solves the goal by invoking the reflexivity of entailment.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_cancel_all : H1 H2 H3 H4,
  H1 \* H2 \* H3 \* H4 ==> H4 \* H3 \* H1 \* H2.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Qed.

xsimpl Instantiates Pure Facts and Quantifiers in the RHS

The third feature of xsimpl is its ability to extract pure facts from the RHS as separate subgoals and to instantiate existential quantifiers from the RHS.
Let us first illustrate how it deals with pure facts. In the example below, the fact n > 0 gets spawned in a separated subgoal.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_hpure : H1 H2 H3 (n:int),
  H1 ==> H2 \* \[n > 0] \* H3.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Abort.
When it encounters an existential quantifier in the RHS, the xsimpl tactic introduces a unification variable denoted by a question mark, that is, an "evar", in Coq terminology. Here, xsimpl turns \ n, .. p ~~> n .. into .. p ~~> ?Goal .., where ?Goal is the evar.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_hexists : H1 H2 H3 H4 (p:loc),
  H1 ==> H2 \* \ (n:int), (p ~~> n \* H3) \* H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
The output of the command Show Existentials shows Existential 1, named ?Goal, of type int. This "evar" corresponds to the value assigned to the existentially quantified variable n.
Abort.
The "evar" often gets subsequently instantiated as a result of a cancellation step. For example, in the example below, xsimpl instantiates the existentially quantified variable n as ?Goal, then cancels out p ~~> ?Goal from the LHS against p ~~> 3 on the right-hand-side, thereby unifying ?Goal with 3. As a result, the "evar" ?Goal is never visible.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_hexists_unify : H1 H2 H3 H4 (p:loc),
  H1 \* (p ~~> 3) ==> H2 \* \ (n:int), (p ~~> n \* H3) \* H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Abort.
The instantiation of "evars" can only be observed if there is another occurrence of the same variable in the entailment. In the next example, which refines the previous one, observe how the assertion n > 0 that appears in the LHS gets turned into the proof obligation 3 > 0. This results from n being unified with 3 when p ~~> n is cancelled against p ~~> 3.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_hexists_unify_view : H1 H2 H4 (p:loc),
  H1 \* (p ~~> 3) ==> H2 \* \ (n:int), (p ~~> n \* \[n > 0]) \* H4.
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl.
Abort.
In practice, in most cases, xsimpl would instantiate existentials on the left-hand side, then discharge what remains of the entailment. Here are two typical examples.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_exists_solved_1 : (p:loc),
  p ~~> 3 ==>
  \ (n:int), p ~~> n.
Proof using. xsimpl. Qed.

Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_exists_solved_2 : (p q:loc),
  p ~~> 3 \* q ~~> 3 ==>
  \ (n:int), p ~~> n \* q ~~> n.
Proof using. xsimpl. Qed.
In certain situations, it may be desirable to provide an explicit value for instantiating an existential quantifier that occurs in the RHS. The xsimpl tactic accepts arguments, which will be used to instantiate the existentials (on a first-match basis). The syntax is xsimpl v1 .. vn.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_hints : H1 (p q:loc),
  H1 ==> \ (n m:int), (p ~~> n \* q ~~> m).
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl 8 9.
Abort.
If two existential quantifiers quantify variables of the same type, it is possible to provide a value for only the second quantifier by passing as first argument to xsimpl the special value __. The following example shows how, on LHS of the form \ n m, ..., the tactic xsimpl __ 9 instantiates m with 9 while leaving n as an unresolved evar.
Lemma xsimpl_demo_rhs_hints_evar : H1 (p q:loc),
  H1 ==> \ (n m:int), (p ~~> n \* q ~~> m).
Proof using.
  intros. xsimpl __ 9.
Abort.

xsimpl on Entailments Between Postconditions

The tactic xsimpl also applies on goals of the form Q1 ===> Q2.
For such goals, it unfolds the definition of ===> to reveal an entailment of the form ==>, then invokes the xsimpl tactic.
Lemma qimpl_example_1 : (Q1 Q2:valhprop) (H2 H3:hprop),
  Q1 \*+ H2 ===> Q2 \*+ H2 \*+ H3.
Proof using. intros. xsimpl. intros r. Abort.

Example: Entailment Proofs using xpull and xsimpl

The xpull tactic is a restricted version of xsimpl: it operates on the left-hand side of the entailment, but leaves the right-hand side untouched. In other words, xpull performs only the first half of the work that xsimpl would do.
Lemma xpull_example_1 : (p:loc),
  \ (n:int), p ~~> n ==>
  \ (m:int), p ~~> (m + 1).
Proof using.
  intros. xpull.
Abort.

Lemma xpull_example_2 : (H:hprop),
  \[False] ==> H.
Proof using. xpull. Qed.
The next example illustrates an interesting situation where xpull is required because a plain call to xsimpl leads to an awkward goal. This examples involves a nontrivial instantiation of an existential quantifier on the right-hand side of the entailment. However, we cannot provide an explicit hint to xsimpl before extracting an existential quantifier that appears on the left-hand side of the entailment. Here is the example.
Lemma xpull_example_3 : (p:loc),
  (\ (n:int), p ~~> n) ==>
  (\ (m:int), p ~~> (m + 1)).
Proof using.
  intros.
  (* xsimpl. *)
Invoking xsimpl here leaves the goal x, x = ?Goal + 1. This statement is technically provable, because ?Goal can be instantiated with x - 1. Yet, discharging such a proof obligation, which features a Coq meta-variable ?Goal that depends on a bound variable x is rather awkward and impractical. The proper route to solving this kind of entailment is to first extract the \ n into the context, then use xsimpl (n-1) to provide as hint to xsimpl that m should be instantiated with n-1.
  xpull. intros n. xsimpl (n-1). math.
Qed.

The xchange Tactic

The tactic xchange is to entailment what rewrite is to equality.
Assume an entailment goal of the form H1 \* H2 \* H3 ==> H4. Assume an entailment assumption M, say H2 ==> H2'. Then xchange M turns the goal into H1 \* H2' \* H3 ==> H4, effectively replacing H2 with H2'.
Lemma xchange_demo_base : H1 H2 H2' H3 H4,
  H2 ==> H2'
  H1 \* H2 \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  introv M. xchange M.
  (* Note that freshly produced items appear to the front *)
Abort.
The xchange tactic can also take an equality as an argument; xchange M exploits the left-to-right direction of an equality M, whereas xchange <- M exploits the right-to-left direction.
Lemma xchange_demo_eq : H1 H2 H3 H4 H5,
  H1 \* H3 = H5
  H1 \* H2 \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  introv M. xchange M.
  xchange <- M.
Abort.
The tactic xchange M will accept a lemma or hypothesis M with universal quantifiers, as long as its conclusion is an equality or an entailment. In such case, xchange M instantiates M before attemting to perform a replacement.
Lemma xchange_demo_inst : H1 (J J':inthprop) H3 H4,
  ( n, J n = J' (n+1))
  H1 \* J 3 \* H3 ==> H4.
Proof using.
  introv M. xchange M.
Abort.

Identifying True and False Entailments

Quiz: For each entailment below, indicate (without a Coq proof) whether it is true or false. Solutions appear further on.
Module EntailmentQuiz.

Implicit Types p q : loc.
Implicit Types n m : int.

Parameter case_study_1 : p q,
      p ~~> 3 \* q ~~> 4
  ==> q ~~> 4 \* p ~~> 3.

Parameter case_study_2 : p q,
      p ~~> 3
  ==> q ~~> 4 \* p ~~> 3.

Parameter case_study_3 : p q,
      q ~~> 4 \* p ~~> 3
  ==> p ~~> 3.

Parameter case_study_4 : p q,
      \[False] \* p ~~> 3
  ==> p ~~> 4 \* q ~~> 4.

Parameter case_study_5 : p q,
      p ~~> 3 \* q ~~> 4
  ==> \[False].

Parameter case_study_6 : p,
      p ~~> 3 \* p ~~> 4
  ==> \[False].

Parameter case_study_7 : p,
      p ~~> 3 \* p ~~> 3
  ==> \[False].

Parameter case_study_8 : p,
      p ~~> 3
  ==> \ n, p ~~> n.

Parameter case_study_9 : p,
       n, p ~~> n
  ==> p ~~> 3.

Parameter case_study_10 : p,
      \ n, p ~~> n \* \[n > 0]
  ==> \ n, \[n > 1] \* p ~~> (n-1).

Parameter case_study_11 : p q,
      p ~~> 3 \* q ~~> 3
  ==> \ n, p ~~> n \* q ~~> n.

Parameter case_study_12 : p n,
      p ~~> n \* \[n > 0] \* \[n < 0]
  ==> p ~~> n \* p ~~> n.

End EntailmentQuiz.

Module EntailmentQuizAnswers.
The answers to the quiz are as follows.
1. True, by commutativity.
2. False, because one cell does not entail two cells.
3. False, because two cells do not entail one cell.
4. True, because \False entails anything.
5. False, because a satisfiable heap predicate does not entail \False.
6. True, because a cell cannot be starred with itself.
7. True, because a cell cannot be starred with itself.
8. True, by instantiating n with 3.
9. False, because n could be something else than 3.
10. True, by instantiating n in RHS with n+1 for the n of the LHS.
11. True, by instantiating n with 3.
12. True, because it is equivalent to \[False] ==> \[False].
Proofs for the true results appear below, using the xsimpl tactic.
Implicit Types p q : loc.
Implicit Types n m : int.

Lemma case_study_1 : p q,
      p ~~> 3 \* q ~~> 4
  ==> q ~~> 4 \* p ~~> 3.
Proof using. xsimpl. Qed.

Lemma case_study_4 : p q,
      \[False] \* p ~~> 3
  ==> p ~~> 4 \* q ~~> 4.
Proof using. xsimpl. Qed.

Lemma case_study_6 : p,
      p ~~> 3 \* p ~~> 4
  ==> \[False].
Proof using. intros. xchange (hstar_hsingle_same_loc p). Qed.

Lemma case_study_7 : p,
      p ~~> 3 \* p ~~> 3
  ==> \[False].
Proof using. intros. xchange (hstar_hsingle_same_loc p). Qed.

Lemma case_study_8 : p,
      p ~~> 3
  ==> \ n, p ~~> n.
Proof using. xsimpl. Qed.

Lemma case_study_10 : p,
      \ n, p ~~> n \* \[n > 0]
  ==> \ n, \[n > 1] \* p ~~> (n-1).
Proof using.
  intros. xpull. intros n Hn. xsimpl (n+1).
  math. math.
Qed.

Lemma case_study_11 : p q,
      p ~~> 3 \* q ~~> 3
  ==> \ n, p ~~> n \* q ~~> n.
Proof using. xsimpl. Qed.

Lemma case_study_12 : p n,
  p ~~> n \* \[n > 0] \* \[n < 0] ==> p ~~> n \* p ~~> n.
Proof using. intros. xsimpl. intros Hn1 Hn2. false. math. Qed.

End EntailmentQuizAnswers.

More Details

Proving Entailments by Hand

Module EntailmentProofs.
Implicit Types p : loc.
Implicit Types n : int.
Proving an entailment by hand is generally a tedious task. This is why most frameworks based on Separation Logic include an automated tactic for simplifying entailments. In this course, the relevant tactic is named xsimpl. In order to fully appreciate what a simplification tactic provides and better understand how it works internally, it is very useful to complete a few entailment proofs by hand.

Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (himpl_example_1)

Prove the example entailment below. Hint: exploit hstar_comm, hstar_assoc, or hstar_comm_assoc which combines the two, and exploit himpl_frame_l or himpl_frame_r to cancel out matching pieces.
Lemma himpl_example_1 : p1 p2 p3 p4,
      p1 ~~> 6 \* p2 ~~> 7 \* p3 ~~> 8 \* p4 ~~> 9
  ==> p4 ~~> 9 \* p3 ~~> 8 \* p2 ~~> 7 \* p1 ~~> 6.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (himpl_example_2)

Prove the example entailment below. Hint: use himpl_hstar_hpure_l to extract pure facts, once they appear at the head of the left-hand side of the entailment. For arithmetic inequalities, use the math tactic.
Lemma himpl_example_2 : p1 p2 p3 n,
      p1 ~~> 6 \* \[n > 0] \* p2 ~~> 7 \* \[n < 0]
  ==> p3 ~~> 8.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (himpl_example_3)

Prove the example entailment below. Hint: use himpl_hexists_r, himpl_hexists_l, himpl_hstar_hpure_l and/or himpl_hstar_hpure_r to deal with pure facts and quantifiers. You may find the TLC tactic math_rewrite (n+1-1 = n) helpful here.
Lemma himpl_example_3 : p,
      \ n, p ~~> n \* \[n > 0]
  ==> \ n, \[n > 1] \* p ~~> (n-1).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Inside the xchange Tactic

How does the xchange tactic work? Consider a goal of the form H ==> H' and assume xchange is invoked with an hypothesis of type H1 ==> H1' as argument. It attempts to decompose H as the star of H1 and the rest of H, call it H2. If it succeeds, then the goal H ==> H' can be rewritten as H1 \* H2 ==> H'. To exploit the hypothesis H1 ==> H1', the tactic should replace the goal with the entailment H1' \* H2 ==> H'. The lemma below mimics this piece of reasoning.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (xchange_lemma)

Prove the following lemma without using xchange.
Lemma xchange_lemma : H1 H1' H H' H2,
  H1 ==> H1'
  H ==> H1 \* H2
  H1' \* H2 ==> H'
  H ==> H'.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Optional Material

Proofs of Rules for Entailment

We next show the details of the proofs establishing some of the fundamental properties of Separation Logic operators. All these results must be proved without help of xsimpl, because the implementation of xsimpl itself depends on these properties.
We begin with the frame property, which is the simplest to prove.

Exercise: 1 star, standard, especially useful (himpl_frame_l)

Prove the frame property for entailment. Hint: unfold the definition of hstar.
Lemma himpl_frame_l : H2 H1 H1',
  H1 ==> H1'
  (H1 \* H2) ==> (H1' \* H2).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
The lemma himpl_frame_l admits two useful corollaries, presented next.

Exercise: 1 star, standard, especially useful (himpl_frame_r)

Prove himpl_frame_r, which is the symmetric of himpl_frame_l.
Lemma himpl_frame_r : H1 H2 H2',
  H2 ==> H2'
  (H1 \* H2) ==> (H1 \* H2').
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 1 star, standard, especially useful (himpl_frame_lr)

The monotonicity property of the star operator w.r.t. entailment can also be stated in a symmetric fashion, as shown next. Prove this result. Hint: exploit the transitivity of entailment (himpl_trans) and the asymmetric monotonicity results from the two prior exercises.
Lemma himpl_frame_lr : H1 H1' H2 H2',
  H1 ==> H1'
  H2 ==> H2'
  (H1 \* H2) ==> (H1' \* H2').
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Historical Notes

(* 2024-08-25 14:53 *)